Libertarianism for Dummies ! (and a refresher for the rest of us!)
Fergus Hodgson
January 26, 2011
Ron Paul didn’t come out of thin air; Fergus Hodgson reviews a new book on the growing influence of libertarianism….
Stories
Libertarianism for Dummies ! (and a refresher for the rest of us!)
Fergus Hodgson
January 26, 2011
Ron Paul didn’t come out of thin air; Fergus Hodgson reviews a new book on the growing influence of libertarianism….
Share on Facebook
Share on Twitter
A review of Jacob Huebert’s Libertarianism Today, 241 pages, Praeger
Reviewed by Fergus Hodgson
When United States 2008 presidential contender Ron Paul raised US $6 million in a single day, an all-time American record, his opponents and the electorate noticed. A former Libertarian Party presidential candidate had made it on the big stage, and with a unique message of peace, freedom, and prosperity.Suddenly “libertarian” entered mainstream parlance, an ideology few people had heard of or understood but which he represented.
Even users of the word seem to disagree so much that “debatarian” would appear more appropriate: anarchists versus minarchists, natural rights advocates versus utilitarians, and it goes on. The intricacies of these disputes and the underlying moralism are likely to perplex and turn off the unacquainted. With Libertarianism Today, Jacob Huebert wades into these murky waters, resists unwarranted accusatory language, and emerges with an accessible yet rigorous explanation of libertarianism and its political movement.
Huebert wrote the book with newcomers in mind and assumes no prior knowledge of political science or economics. It is for those “who are curious as to what libertarianism is… and “walks them through it,” says Huebert. The book is, however, more than just a primer, and even long-time libertarians will find plenty to digest, particularly from the account of the libertarian political movement.
Huebert divides his book broadly into two sections: the underlying libertarian idea and then its application to prominent, contemporary issues. He deliberately wrote it to be current, so the idea’s application is wrapped in controversies we can relate to and that still feature prominently in political discourse.
“Every day, in nearly every way, government only gets bigger and more inhumane,” he begins. But “libertarians do have some cause for hope – more now, perhaps, than at any other point in our lifetimes.” The 2008 Ron Paul presidential campaign was, in his view, grounded in a clear philosophy, and it demonstrated that libertarianism is a credible alternative to the standard party lines. The campaign’s constituent driven success also testified to a broad-based and growing pro-liberty movement, from the growth of homeschooling to the migration of libertarians to the American state of New Hampshire.
The libertarian alternative is that “anyone should be free to do anything he or she wants, as long as he or she does not commit acts of force or fraud against any other peaceful person.” This “non-aggression principle” seems widely acceptable at face value, and in “everyday life, people understand and follow this basic libertarian rule… If you do not like the books your neighbor is reading, or the religion he is practicing, or most anything else he is doing in the privacy or his own home, too bad.”
Libertarians, however, apply this idea to the political realm, and that is where the conflict with conventional politics begins. For example, “if one person cannot steal money from another, then the government (which is made up of individual people) should not be allowed to forcibly take money from people, even if it is called taxation.” From this perspective, politicians are the criminals preying on innocent individuals, regardless of whether their activities are legalized.
Huebert acknowledges, though, that those subscribing to this basic libertarian idea arrive from many perspectives, including economic reasoning, Randian objectivism, religious values, and natural rights theory. Thus, their different interpretations are to be predicted, and many libertarians are willing to accept a minimal “night watchman state,” providing for national defense, police, and courts. He does not wish to concern himself with the dispute between no-government libertarians (anarchists) and minimal-government libertarians (minarchists) but he will say that the maintenance or increase of government’s power is anti-libertarian.
Huebert rightly warns readers that libertarianism is “not a complete moral philosophy or a philosophy of life.” As a political philosophy, it does not dictate how one ought to live within peaceful activity. His explanation, although technically correct, may confuse readers, since at the same time he asserts the immorality of commonplace institutions such as government schools. Jan Narveson, Canada’s leading libertarian intellectual and professor emeritus of the University of Waterloo, Ontario, provides a clearer explanation: “To refrain from aggression against others, that is obviously a moral principle… what is meant is that within the limits imposed by a prohibition against aggression, we may choose as we please.”
Correspondingly, Huebert points out that libertarianism is not libertinism. It does not infer, for example, whether or not individuals ought to consume drugs, even if it calls for complete legalization. Again, this point may be counterintuitive to many readers—all the more reason to read the book. Keep in mind that from a libertarian perspective, morality, wherever it may come from, is not determined by a nation’s rulers (no divine right of kings). Nor is it determined by a show of hands.
The second chapter “Libertarians are not conservatives (or liberals)” examines the different strains and evolution of modern conservatism and the perception that libertarians are merely radical conservatives. This chapter is brimming with valuable insights into the key players and ideological undercurrents of conservatism, and it even addresses the divisive and ideologically important topics of gay marriage and abortion.
While Huebert concludes that libertarianism and conservatism are not even very similar, he does acknowledge that many libertarians are culturally conservative. This discussion is particularly important because conservatism is more likely than contemporary liberalism to absorb the growing popularity of libertarianism, as has occurred with the American Tea Party movement. For those disaffected by moral decadence and an entitlement mentality, a libertarian society would eliminate government programs that attack traditional institutions and conservative personal values.
In Canada, supporters of Canada’s Institute for Liberal Studies, a promoter of liberalism in the classical, liberty-oriented tradition, will appreciate that Huebert also assesses how use of “liberal” has morphed. Indeed, libertarians were the original liberals, and classical liberalism had nothing to with a welfare state or the imposition of social values.
Huebert then mixes the ideology with what he sees as the most relevant political issues, such as economic prosperity, health care, education, drug policy, and war. He also addresses areas of notable dispute or confusion in the application of libertarianism, such as intellectual property and whether one ought to participate in politics. Immigration is a surprising omission, since it is both timely and a matter of dispute.
These chapters provide antidotes to many myths that circulate with limited rebuttal. The notion that libertarians and free markets are responsible for the latest economic crisis is one example—as though libertarians advocate a central bank and fiat currency, let alone government-sponsored loan agencies.
“Libertarians have not been running the show in Washington,” writes Huebert. Nor have they been running the show anywhere else. “In fact, before the crisis, libertarians were nearly alone in condemning the main policies that led to it.”
The support of libertarians for big business is another debunked myth. So long as these enterprises are compatible with genuine free market capitalism, fine. But since so many seek subsidies, bailouts, and other forms of coerced largesse, they do not carry the banner of libertarianism.
At times these chapters do not make for pleasant reading, but that reflects an intellectual honesty on Huebert’s part, an unwillingness to gloss over the darker side of government actions. For example, he documents the militarization of the United States police force, particularly on account of the “war on drugs,” including the transfer of aircraft, machine guns, and grenade launchers. And he tells of how this expanded power came with the price of endless tragic stories for people not even involved in drug activities.
At odds with the anti-nationalism theme, Huebert’s emphasis throughout is almost solely on the United States, especially in the applied chapters. While he admits his anarchist orientation (and presumed support for open borders) his references to events or thinkers in neighboring nations such as Canada are few and leaves much to be desired. The Fraser Institute and its economic freedom index receive a mention, but that’s it; this lack of interest propagates the stereotype that the rest of the world is lost on Americans.
The front cover, colored with the American flag, further highlights this shortcoming. Potential readers would do well to resist swift judgment, since the underlying theme does go beyond geographical location. Narveson is one Canadian who still hopes the book will be widely read and understood, but Huebert’s focus on incremental court battles and intricacies of American politics, probably on account of his law profession, based in Ohio, is the greatest flaw of Libertarianism Today.
What Libertarianism Today has to offer, though, far overweighs this flaw. Huebert’s work is worthy of promotion as an accurate, easily readable, and up-to-date introduction to a movement of growing relevance.
As Canadian universities descend into apparent madness – hiring for skin colour rather than merit, enforcing draconian speech codes and unravelling the ancient protection of academic tenure – one voice has been resolute in demanding a return to higher standards in higher education. Mark Mercer, president of the Society for Academic Freedom and Scholarship since 2015, has proved Canada’s pre-eminent defender of Enlightenment values throughout the academy. In a wide-ranging discussion with C2C Journal’s Patrick Keeney, Mercer charts the origins of our current Woke revolution, the overarching significance of academic freedom and how its loss is affecting life both on and off campus. It may not be a happy story, but it is a necessary one.
The coronation of King Charles III led many Canadians to ask, once again, a simple question: Why should an old man in a land across the sea be our head of state, simply because his ancestors were? It’s a good question, and the case against the monarchy seems powerful. Jamie C. Weir takes on the key arguments and explains why an antiquated and undemocratic institution remains the centrepiece of Canada’s unique political culture, provides a profound and even magical link to our past, and serves as an essential bulwark against the two political death-traps of anarchy and tyranny.
Canadians, we are often told, are a caring and sharing people. Perhaps Canada’s federal workers and their union bosses failed to read the memo, for their recent behaviour has been the opposite: callous and greedy. After coasting through the pandemic “working from home” on full salary, Canada’s “public servants” threw tantrums over returning to the office, demanded an enormous pay increase – then went on strike and blockaded federal facilities. This week they came out of the process richer and even more coddled. Gwyn Morgan charts the federal government’s cave-in to its unionized employees and the ever-growing disparity in compensation between them and the private-sector workers who are taxed to pay for it all. Part II of a special series (Part I is here).
A French schoolteacher was beheaded for showing his class cartoons caricaturing the Prophet Mohammed. This barbaric act has finally compelled Justin Trudeau to defend free speech, reversing his previous equivocation. Fergus Hodgson warns that government and the media are already complicit in restricting speech under such guises as “hate speech,” “discrimination” and “misgendering.”
The homeless of Canada, as a growing and suffering demographic, warrant our concern. Contrary to public perceptions, approximately half of these individuals are employed, and even more are willing to work. However, since the cost of housing has greatly outpaced wage growth, minimum wage and low paying jobs are no longer sufficient to cover accommodation in many of Canada’s major cities. The homeless are primarily a symptom of a restrained housing supply, particularly the low-cost variety. While numerous government programs and community initiatives have sought to address homelessness, they have proved ineffectual and often counterproductive. The homeless population has continued to expand, along with the relevant waiting lists and government agencies. These initiatives will continue to fail while the underlying cause, the many impediments to and the lack of private housing, is not addressed.